When.com Web Search

Search results

  1. Results From The WOW.Com Content Network
  2. Axiomatic system - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Axiomatic_system

    An axiomatic system is said to be consistent if it lacks contradiction.That is, it is impossible to derive both a statement and its negation from the system's axioms. Consistency is a key requirement for most axiomatic systems, as the presence of contradiction would allow any statement to be proven (principle of explo

  3. Gödel's incompleteness theorems - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Gödel's_incompleteness...

    The ω-consistency of a system implies its consistency, but consistency does not imply ω-consistency. J. Barkley Rosser strengthened the incompleteness theorem by finding a variation of the proof (Rosser's trick) that only requires the system to be consistent, rather than ω-consistent. This is mostly of technical interest, because all true ...

  4. Foundations of geometry - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Foundations_of_geometry

    Except in the simplest systems, consistency is a difficult property to establish in an axiomatic system. On the other hand, if a model exists for the axiomatic system, then any contradiction derivable in the system is also derivable in the model, and the axiomatic system is as consistent as any system in which the model belongs.

  5. Consistency - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Consistency

    Because consistency of ZF is not provable in ZF, the weaker notion relative consistency is interesting in set theory (and in other sufficiently expressive axiomatic systems). If T is a theory and A is an additional axiom , T + A is said to be consistent relative to T (or simply that A is consistent with T ) if it can be proved that if T is ...

  6. Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Zermelo–Fraenkel_set_theory

    In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes such as Russell's paradox.

  7. Tarski's axioms - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Tarski's_axioms

    Let wff stand for a well-formed formula (or syntactically correct first-order formula) in Tarski's system. Tarski and Givant (1999: 175) proved that Tarski's system is: Consistent: There is no wff such that it and its negation can both be proven from the axioms; Complete: Every wff or its negation is a theorem provable from the axioms;

  8. Kurt Gödel - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Kurt_Gödel

    In that article, he proved for any computable axiomatic system that is powerful enough to describe the arithmetic of the natural numbers (e.g., the Peano axioms or Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice), that: If a (logical or axiomatic formal) system is omega-consistent, it cannot be syntactically complete.

  9. Hilbert's axioms - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Hilbert's_axioms

    The value of the Grundlagen is its pioneering approach to metamathematical questions, including the use of models to prove axioms independent; and the need to prove the consistency and completeness of an axiom system. Mathematics in the twentieth century evolved into a network of axiomatic formal systems.