When.com Web Search

Search results

  1. Results From The WOW.Com Content Network
  2. Skolem's paradox - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Skolem's_paradox

    One of the earliest results in set theory, published by Cantor in 1874, was the existence of different sizes, or cardinalities, of infinite sets. [2] An infinite set is called countable if there is a function that gives a one-to-one correspondence between and the natural numbers, and is uncountable if there is no such correspondence function.

  3. Continuum hypothesis - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Continuum_hypothesis

    The rational numbers seemingly form a counterexample to the continuum hypothesis: the integers form a proper subset of the rationals, which themselves form a proper subset of the reals, so intuitively, there are more rational numbers than integers and more real numbers than rational numbers.

  4. Löwenheim–Skolem theorem - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Löwenheim–Skolem_theorem

    It is called countable if the set of function and relation symbols in it is countable, and in general the cardinality of a signature is the cardinality of the set of all the symbols it contains. A first-order theory consists of a fixed signature and a fixed set of sentences (formulas with no free variables) in that signature.

  5. Inaccessible cardinal - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Inaccessible_cardinal

    In set theory, an uncountable cardinal is inaccessible if it cannot be obtained from smaller cardinals by the usual operations of cardinal arithmetic.More precisely, a cardinal κ is strongly inaccessible if it satisfies the following three conditions: it is uncountable, it is not a sum of fewer than κ cardinals smaller than κ, and < implies <.

  6. Spectrum of a theory - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Spectrum_of_a_theory

    By extending Shelah's work, Bradd Hart, Ehud Hrushovski and Michael C. Laskowski gave the following complete solution to the spectrum problem for countable theories in uncountable cardinalities. If T is a countable complete theory, then the number I( T , ℵ α ) of isomorphism classes of models is given for ordinals α>0 by the minimum of 2 ...

  7. Subcountability - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Subcountability

    Being countable implies being subcountable. In the appropriate context with Markov's principle , the converse is equivalent to the law of excluded middle , i.e. that for all proposition ϕ {\displaystyle \phi } holds ϕ ∨ ¬ ϕ {\displaystyle \phi \lor \neg \phi } .

  8. Cantor's diagonal argument - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Cantor's_diagonal_argument

    The former relate to quotients of sequences while the later are well-behaved cuts taken from a powerset, if they exist. In the presence of excluded middle, those are all isomorphic and uncountable. Otherwise, variants of the Dedekind reals can be countable [15] or inject into the naturals, but not jointly.

  9. Infinite set - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Infinite_set

    If the axiom of choice holds, then a set is infinite if and only if it includes a countable infinite subset. If a set of sets is infinite or contains an infinite element, then its union is infinite. The power set of an infinite set is infinite. [3] Any superset of an infinite set is infinite. If an infinite set is partitioned into finitely many ...