Search results
Results From The WOW.Com Content Network
In mathematics, a set A is a subset of a set B if all elements of A are also elements of B; B is then a superset of A. It is possible for A and B to be equal; if they are unequal, then A is a proper subset of B. The relationship of one set being a subset of another is called inclusion (or sometimes containment).
If A is a subset of B, then one can also say that B is a superset of A, that A is contained in B, or that B contains A. In symbols, A ⊆ B means that A is a subset of B, and B ⊇ A means that B is a superset of A. Some authors use the symbols ⊂ and ⊃ for subsets, and others use these symbols only for proper subsets. For clarity, one can ...
A third pair of operators ⊂ and ⊃ are used differently by different authors: some authors use A ⊂ B and B ⊃ A to mean A is any subset of B (and not necessarily a proper subset), [34] [12] while others reserve A ⊂ B and B ⊃ A for cases where A is a proper subset of B. [33] Examples: The set of all humans is a proper subset of the set ...
The algebra of sets is the set-theoretic analogue of the algebra of numbers. Just as arithmetic addition and multiplication are associative and commutative, so are set union and intersection; just as the arithmetic relation "less than or equal" is reflexive, antisymmetric and transitive, so is the set relation of "subset".
2. A proper subset of a set X is a subset not equal to X. 3. A proper forcing is a forcing notion that does not collapse any stationary set 4. The proper forcing axiom asserts that if P is proper and D α is a dense subset of P for each α<ω 1, then there is a filter G P such that D α ∩ G is nonempty for all α<ω 1
In constructive mathematics, "not empty" and "inhabited" are not equivalent: every inhabited set is not empty but the converse is not always guaranteed; that is, in constructive mathematics, a set that is not empty (where by definition, "is empty" means that the statement () is true) might not have an inhabitant (which is an such that ).
A simple example is , the set of natural numbers. From Galileo's paradox , there exists a bijection that maps every natural number n to its square n 2 . Since the set of squares is a proper subset of N {\displaystyle \mathbb {N} } , N {\displaystyle \mathbb {N} } is Dedekind-infinite.
A partition of a set X is a set of non-empty subsets of X such that every element x in X is in exactly one of these subsets [2] (i.e., the subsets are nonempty mutually disjoint sets). Equivalently, a family of sets P is a partition of X if and only if all of the following conditions hold: [3]