When.com Web Search

Search results

  1. Results From The WOW.Com Content Network
  2. Validity (logic) - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Validity_(logic)

    If also the premises of a valid argument are proven true, this is said to be sound. [3] The corresponding conditional of a valid argument is a logical truth and the negation of its corresponding conditional is a contradiction. The conclusion is a necessary consequence of its premises. An argument that is not valid is said to be "invalid".

  3. Premise - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Premise

    An example of this is the use of the rules of inference found within symbolic logic. Aristotle held that any logical argument could be reduced to two premises and a conclusion. [2] Premises are sometimes left unstated, in which case, they are called missing premises, for example: Socrates is mortal because all men are mortal.

  4. Paradoxes of material implication - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Paradoxes_of_material...

    Validity is defined in classical logic as follows: An argument (consisting of premises and a conclusion) is valid if and only if there is no possible situation in which all the premises are true and the conclusion is false. For example a valid argument might run: If it is raining, water exists (1st premise) It is raining (2nd premise)

  5. False premise - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/False_premise

    However, the logical validity of an argument is a function of its internal consistency, not the truth value of its premises. For example, consider this syllogism, which involves a false premise: If the streets are wet, it has rained recently. (premise) The streets are wet. (premise) Therefore it has rained recently. (conclusion)

  6. Argument - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Argument

    If yes, the argument is strong. If no, it is weak. A strong argument is said to be cogent if it has all true premises. Otherwise, the argument is uncogent. The military budget argument example is a strong, cogent argument. Non-deductive logic is reasoning using arguments in which the premises support the conclusion but do not entail it.

  7. Soundness - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Soundness

    An example of a sound argument is the following well-known syllogism: (premises) All men are mortal. Socrates is a man. (conclusion) Therefore, Socrates is mortal. Because of the logical necessity of the conclusion, this argument is valid; and because the argument is valid and its premises are true, the argument is sound.

  8. Rule of inference - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Rule_of_inference

    For example, the rule of inference called modus ponens takes two premises, one in the form "If p then q" and another in the form "p", and returns the conclusion "q". The rule is valid with respect to the semantics of classical logic (as well as the semantics of many other non-classical logics ), in the sense that if the premises are true (under ...

  9. Philosophy of logic - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Philosophy_of_logic

    In this formalism, the validity of arguments only depends on the structure of the argument, specifically on the logical constants used in the premises and the conclusion. [2] [5] On this view, a proposition is a logical consequence of a group of premises if and only if the proposition is deducible from these premises. [20]