When.com Web Search

Search results

  1. Results From The WOW.Com Content Network
  2. Disjunctive syllogism - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Disjunctive_syllogism

    In classical logic, disjunctive syllogism [1] [2] (historically known as modus tollendo ponens (MTP), [3] Latin for "mode that affirms by denying") [4] is a valid argument form which is a syllogism having a disjunctive statement for one of its premises. [5] [6] An example in English: I will choose soup or I will choose salad. I will not choose ...

  3. List of valid argument forms - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/List_of_valid_argument_forms

    Disjunctive syllogism (sometimes abbreviated DS) has one of the same characteristics as modus tollens in that it contains a premise, then in a second premise it denies a statement, leading to the conclusion. In Disjunctive Syllogism, the first premise establishes two options.

  4. Syllogism - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Syllogism

    A syllogism takes the form (note: M – Middle, S – subject, P – predicate.): Major premise: All M are P. Minor premise: All S are M. Conclusion/Consequent: All S are P. The premises and conclusion of a syllogism can be any of four types, which are labeled by letters [14] as follows. The meaning of the letters is given by the table:

  5. Modus ponens - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Modus_ponens

    Modus ponens is a mixed hypothetical syllogism and is closely related to another valid form of argument, modus tollens. Both have apparently similar but invalid forms: affirming the consequent and denying the antecedent. Constructive dilemma is the disjunctive version of modus ponens. The history of modus ponens goes back to antiquity. [4]

  6. Modus tollens - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Modus_tollens

    The form of a modus tollens argument is a mixed hypothetical syllogism, with two premises and a conclusion: . If P, then Q. Not Q. Therefore, not P.. The first premise is a conditional ("if-then") claim, such as P implies Q.

  7. Principle of explosion - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Principle_of_explosion

    However, since we also know that "Not all lemons are yellow" (as this has been assumed), the first part is false, and hence the second part must be true to ensure the two-part statement to be true, i.e., unicorns exist (this inference is known as the Disjunctive syllogism).

  8. List of rules of inference - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/List_of_rules_of_inference

    Rules of inference are syntactical transform rules which one can use to infer a conclusion from a premise to create an argument. A set of rules can be used to infer any valid conclusion if it is complete, while never inferring an invalid conclusion, if it is sound.

  9. False dilemma - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/False_dilemma

    disjunctive syllogism: (), () In this form, the first premise ( P ∨ Q {\displaystyle P\lor Q} ) is responsible for the fallacious inference. Lewis's trilemma is a famous example of this type of argument involving three disjuncts: "Jesus was either a liar, a lunatic, or Lord". [ 3 ]